January
1, 2011
Dear
Editor;
In
his most recent contribution (31 December 2010), which appeared on your
website, Eskinder Nega raised the question of whether Derg officials were
wrongly convicted of genocide and concluded that �they have been
sentenced to death for the wrong reasons�[and] they are not guilty of
genocide.�
Ethiopian�s-Derg-guilty-of-genocide-or-politicized. This is not an
unfamiliar argument as it was the mainstay of the defense team�s
argument against the charges. Let me first begin by expressing what
I felt about this analysis. It seems to me that the purpose of his
analysis is to present the perpetrators in a positive light so as to
soften public opposition to the apology being requested. One
can simply note the subliminal pressure on the reader in his profiling of
the notorious butcher of Gondar whose infamy has entered in to the local
folklore simply as a pathetic, insecure, and an underachiever young man
not worthy of the maximum punishment a society reserves to its serious
offenders. This may be an unfair assessment of Eskinder�s
intentions and I stand to be corrected. On the other hand, he has not done
anything to dispel the rumor that even at his old age Melaku continues to
be defiant and rejects accusations labeled against him. Again I stand to
be corrected on the veracity of these rumors. Eskinder would have done him
and his lot a favor if he probed deeper and presented evidence that Melaku
is not in league with his former boss Mengistu Hailemariam who publically,
after the guilty verdict, categorically said that he had never killed a
fly let alone a human being. [Mengistu�s Reuters Interview, video widely
available online] Fair enough, and everybody is entitled to their opinion,
but what worries me the most is how the legal arguments were presented to
diminish the significance of whatever crimes they �should have been
guilty of.� I do not think that we should take these lightly.
Genocide is a relatively new term coined by
Rapahel Lemkin, a Polish Jew lawyer, in 1944. This means, all crimes of
genocide that we recognize today such as the Jewish holocaust or the
Armenian genocide were not labeled as such before this term was coined.
Such crimes were known by different names, among others, crimes against
humanity. The NAZI war crimes suspects were not charged and convicted of
genocide. Rather they were charged and found guilty of committing crimes
against peace, waging war of aggression, war crimes and crimes against
humanity. The word genocide, however, came to acquire such a powerful
meaning and connotations so that labeling all types of massive killings as
genocide as opposed to, say, crimes against humanity is becoming very
commonplace. In reality, crimes against humanity is as heinous, grave and
an affront to the conscience of humanity as genocide is. Any argument
which seeks to diminish the moral blameworthiness of individuals who
commit crimes against humanity is unacceptable. For argument sake,
however, it does not make a difference whether Derg officials were
convicted of crimes against humanity or genocide as far as the gravity of
their offence is concerned both under our law and under international law.
Perhaps, for various reasons, there is more stigma attached to genocide
than other forms of mass killings.
On political groups: as Eskinder pointed
out, including political groups among groups protected against genocide
was a controversial subject and it was eventually dropped from the 1948
Genocide Convention due to a political compromise which emanated from a
pressure exerted by the Soviet Block. Ethiopia at the time simply
abstained and did not vote against the exclusion of political groups. But
for Lemkin, the man who coined the word genocide, political groups were
protected against genocide, although he excluded them later in his draft
treaty prepared for the UN out of fear of disagreement by member states.
Here is the original definition from his book: �Axis Rule in Occupied
Europe� (1943):
�Generally speaking, genocide does not
necessarily mean the immediate destruction of a nation, except when
accomplished by mass killings of all members of a nation. It is intended
rather to signify a coordinated plan of different actions aiming at the
destruction of essential foundations of the life of national groups, with
the aim of annihilating the groups themselves. The objectives of such a
plan would be the disintegration of the political and social institutions,
of culture, language, national feelings, religion, and the economic
existence of national groups, and the destruction of the personal
security, liberty, health, dignity, and even the lives of the individuals
belonging to such groups.�
Furthermore, in 1946, when the
General Assembly of the United Nations called for a convention on genocide
on its 11 December 1946 resolution, it explicitly included crimes
committed on political grounds as crimes of genocide punishable under
international law.
Be this as it may, Ethiopia, along with a
handful of other countries such as, France (Art. 211-1 of its Penal Code)
and Bolivia moved to include political groups in the category of groups
protected against genocide. Considering all these, and the fact that the
Ethiopian Penal Code of 1957 pre-existed the commission of the crimes,
there is no legal ground for disputing that the suspects could not be
charged with genocide. Yes, our law is not co-extensive with the
genocide convention or the national laws of other countries which excluded
political groups from protection, but it does not contradict any rule of
international law and it better protects Ethiopian citizens.
Eskinder also took issue with whether the
number of victims fulfilled the threshold for genocide and obliquely
referred to the jurisprudence of the International Criminal Tribunal for
the Former Yugoslavia to support his argument. This could pass for a
respectable argument in defense of the suspects before any court of law if
pursued rigorously but nonetheless, must fail. The essence of the law
against genocide is not about numbers. It is about the intention to
eliminate protected groups in whole or in part and how far the suspect
goes to realize his or her intentions. We may summarily dismiss the
argument that Derg did not intend to eliminate EPRP or any other political
opposition in whole, because examples show that not everybody who was an
EPRP member died or suffered adverse consequences. But this is immaterial.
In relation to this, however, what Eskinder failed to point out is that
genocide is committed not only by killing- other acts such as
imprisonment, torture, even rape (as was recognized by the Rwanda
Tribunal) so long as those actions were taken to further the genocidal
intent amount to genocide. There is a strong case to show that, Derg
intended to eliminate parts of political groups standing in opposition to
its revolution. It is unrealistic to expect that Derg needed to wipe out
all or a given number of EPRP members to meet the threshold. But at the
very least, it is a matter of common knowledge that it imprisoned those it
identified as members of the opposition in furtherance of its policy of
eliminating EPRP and other opposition groups. Others who were not affected
were mainly because, either they escaped or Derg was not able to lay its
hands on them.
Can one counter the argument that the crime
did not reach the genocidal threshold simply because only less than � of
the member of the group were targeted as asserted by Eskinder? Assuming
that the figures are true, let us look at a case from the Tribunal on
Former Yugoslavia, where only one incident was labeled as genocide while
most others were categorized as crimes against humanity. This was
confirmed by the International Court of Justice as well. In this one
instance relating to the massacre in Srebrenica, the victims mainly men-
including those above 65 and young boys were less than 8000 in number
constituting roughly about 1/5 of the population of the region. The
tribunal in Krstic case driving the message home that number is only the
beginning but not the end of the inquiry observed:
�the numeric size of the targeted part of
the group is the necessary and important starting point, though not in all
cases the ending point of the inquiry. The number of individuals targeted
should be evaluated not only in absolute terms, but also in relation to
the overall size of the entire group. In addition to the numeric size of
the targeted portion, its prominence within the group can be a useful
consideration. If a specific part of the group is emblematic of the
overall group, or is essential to its survival, that may support a finding
that the part qualifies as substantial within the meaning of Article 4.�
So what do we know about the number of
members of the opposition targeted for liquidation, torture, imprisonment,
rape, enforced disappearance etc, in comparison to the EPRP membership? Is
the number and composition of those targeted (including innocent children)
not emblematic of the whole group? Were those who perished not essential
for the survival of the group? Did this terror in fact not succeed in
vanquishing EPRP and the opposition beyond any possibility of recovery? I
think we have our answer.
Eskinder also wrote that the crime
needs to be called politicized instead of genocide following Gurr and
Harff. Politicized is not a legal term and does not carry any punishment
in any modern criminal code. Until that word enters a legal lexicon we
ought to call it what our criminal code calls it.
He also raised an important issue of
prosecutorial discretion. I argued elsewhere that, the argument whether
the acts constituted genocide as it is popularly known or not, is doing a
disservice to the whole debate considering the highly politicized nature
of such trials. The Special Prosecutor had an option of charging
the suspects with commission of crimes against humanity carrying same
punishment as well as no lesser degree of moral blameworthiness. However,
he did what he did and here we are. But let it be
remembered that whether they were found guilty of genocide or crimes
against humanity it does not diminish the extent of their guilt.
In fact, to the contrary, being charged under such a novel and uncommon
provision has helped rally support for them as if they are being taken for
a ride by those implementing �victor�s justice� under a
controversial law. From my readings of the decision of the Federal High
Court, the defense and their witnesses were sometimes wrongly trying to
defend the accusations as if they were charged with trying to eliminate a
particular ethnic group. Their defenses sometimes run like, �Derg did
not have a policy of eliminating any ethnic group�. This was not what
they were charged with and this line of defense in addition to wasting the
defense�s precious time and energy had to an extent also helped in
leaving the wrong perception about the trials. The Amharic word for
genocide �Zero Matfat� which is equivalent to �eliminating a race�
might have also played a role in this.
I agree with Eskinder that the suspects did
not receive adequate legal representation and their case dragged on for
decades. There are also numerous questionable aspects of issues of
individual criminal responsibility which could be a basis for challenging
the verdicts for some of the suspects. The legal procedure is almost
complete unless the Cassation Court says otherwise. Thus, at this stage
the larger debate is the extent to which they are prepared to come clean
of their own accord and whether the victims and the wider society is
prepared to put this behind and move on. One has to do the convincing but
the tone of this otherwise fine analysis by Eskinder Nega did not seem
quite like it.
Firew Kebede Tiba is a Lecturer in
Law at the University of Waikato School of Law in Hamilton, New Zealand.
He could be reached at: [email protected]
==========================
Firew Kebede Tiba, PhD
Lecturer, University of Waikato
Faculty of Law-Te Piringa
Private Bag 3105
Hamilton 3240, New Zealand
Tel: +6478384466
begin_of_the_skype_highlighting +6478384466 end_of_the_skype_highlighting
ext 8094
https://www.waikato.ac.nz/law
|