New
Version
Bonsai
Ethiopia
: A
esthetic Beauty and Artistic
Beauty
[A
Diversion from Fixation on Politics]
By
Tecola W. Hagos
I.
Introduction
In
an earlier article, I had narrated about my visit to the National
Arboretum in
North-East
DC
. Because I started out being overwhelmed with the
Bonsai
Garden
and the majesty of the Pine and the Oak trees and the colorful Azalea, I
decided to investigate up close the concept of �beauty� and the idea
of the �sublime� in our contemporary discourse. Even thinking in those
terms left me feeling that I might as well be dressed in velvet with tight
fitting silk breeches stepping out from the period about the end of the
Enlightenment or even further back from the ancient world dressed in Roman
Toga.
For
our contemporary artists the term �beauty� let alone the concept of
the beautiful ever enter their vocabulary. The other day I was watching a
taped interview/statement of Julie Mehretu, the �American� artist, on
occasion of the opening of her exhibition of six of her recent works at
the Guggenheim Museum NYC, May 14 to October 6, 2010.
What is striking is how very little there was in her statements on
the treatment of the subject of �beauty� in her paintings. She
frequently used terms like �geometric abstraction,� �developing a
language,� �ghost image,� �intuition� et cetera, and these are
familiar sounding terms but used in a supporting role in earlier
discourses. All of her focus was on her craftsmanship and execution. There
is no attempt to share the inner impulse as to what is her aspiration in
her work.
Of
course, it will be foolish to expect a full fledged answer on that from
any artist. �Content� in contemporary art could only be understood as
the presentation itself. There is no moralization, symbolization, or
representation of some grand revealed truth. Despite the fact that
architectural drawing dominated her work, it is obvious that her attempt
is not to recreate blue-prints of beauty. Immensity as an art form has
been in practice for thousands of years�the Pyramids and
Stonehenge
are living evidence. In our own modern era we could start with Mount
Rushmore�s massive sculpted faces of four
United States
Presidents, and move on to temporal environmental art pieces where we had
whole sea-shore dyed, entire country side wrapped in fabric et cetera. For
example, there were memorable works that clearly illustrate the sublime in
art, such as Robert
Smithson�s sculpture Spiral
Jetty
(1969); Christo and Jeanne-Claude�s Running
Fences (1976) et cetera. There we see the effort in creating the
sublime by extension. I think of Julie Mehretu�s humongous tableaux in
the same vein.
The
�end of art� as the philosopher Danto sensed would happen in the
individuated artist separated from society even from patrons, adored and
held in a golden chalice untouchable and fabulously wealthy as part of the
money making setup of the public-relation world. The suffering-artist can
only be found in narrative works of legends. If I am as courageous as I am
cynical, I would say that Danto got it wrong, for he should have stated
�the end of artists� and the birth of celebrities rather than the
�end of art.�
The
very title of this essay would date me as anachronistic, a person from a
different era altogether. For some who read this essay, I might as well
have walked out of the pages of Tolstoy dressed in velvet and silk
breeches with antediluvian ideas about art and artists, and hopelessly
antiquated. Nevertheless, I insist in reexamining fads and trends for
authenticity, for that seems to be the last weapon left in the hands of
individuals genuinely interested in the creative process.
II. Philosophical Interlude of the Beautiful
and the Sublime
Walking
through the Bonsai trees display was a whole new experience. There I
learned with amazement the longevity of some of the Bonsai trees. A
Japanese White Pine, also displayed in the brochure of the Arboretum, was
listed in training since 1625, almost four hundred years old. A number of
Elms, Junipers et cetera were also in training since the 1860s. The
awesome beauty of these Bonsai trees is not describable in words in full;
one must visit and stand in awe in front of such marvels of nature and the
hands of man in order to have a first-hand experience of the
�sublime.�
As
Abraham and I walked through the �sublime� Bonsai Japanese and Chinese
displays, we started to talk about what beauty really is. We ended up in
disagreement, I holding the view that beauty is totally in the mind and
Abraham holding the view that beauty is partly in the thing and partly in
the mind. We did not try to resolve the difference in our ideas of the
beautiful, and we just continued to soak in the beauty and fragrance that
was engulfing us. When we reached the herbal garden our sense of smell was
stimulated to intoxication with fragrances of clumps of Rosemary, Thyme,
Sage, Oregano et cetera.
Earlier,
as we drove down to the Arboretum, Abraham and I discussed the similarity
of trees and children, for we both marveled at the dignity displayed by
children from all walks of life in any community, and how all trees have
that splendid quiet majesty about them. Further into the innards of the
Arboretum, our eyes were dazzled by the stupendous display of color from
red Maples and the Azaleas nestled by the feet of Pines and Oaks. And by
the Azalea garden proper, we came face to face with the towering majesty
of all kinds of pine trees, some were familiar trees to both of us from
our far away Ethiopia and yet very close.
The
question of beauty has preoccupied philosophers from the pre-Socratics to
date in every generation. I suppose that early in mankind�s communal
life, the creative impulse was solely decorative and the enhancement of
the physical presence of the individual, and maybe part of the mating
ritual. In our own time there had been a real revolutionary process that
may be compared to a philosophical convulsion [See Arthur C. Danto, The
abuse of beauty: aesthetics and the concept of art,
Carus (2003)]. Among those who shaped the way the art of the West
is looked at were art critics from the Victorians such as John Ruskin,
from the Romantics such as Kenneth Clark, and from the modernists such as
Clement Greenberg. Greenberg is a serendipitous find, for his pitch to
discredit and discount the effort of �socialist realism� in art as the
corner stone of the Soviet Union�s World of Art, while in the pay of the
CIA, had unexpected outcome�in a very talented and successful art
critic. [See Francis Stonor Saunders, Who
Paid the Piper?: CIA and the Cultural Cold War, Granta Books
(2000); The Cultural Cold War: The CIA and
the World of Arts and Letters,
New Press (2000). See also Richard Cummings, �Art and the CIA,�
June 20, 2002, https://www.lewrockwell.com/orig3/cummings3.html.
It is a snapshot of the page as it appeared on Apr 19, 2010.]
The
more recent approach is declaring the end of art as the philosopher Arthur
C. Danto did in an article in 1984, but some how tamed that earlier
statement away from such provocative assertion in a book he wrote a decade
later [After the end of art: contemporary art and
the pale of history, Princeton
University Press, NJ (1997)]. And I audaciously state that the
history of art shows in varying paces a movement from the thematic to the
anecdotal, and one may throw in there as an afterthought for effect the
early classical ideas on beauty, the different movements since the time of
the impressionists, and the art-for-art sake concepts, then you would have
covered most anything in the history of Western Art. One may even be
cynical saying that what I have stated is no different than Hegel�s idea
of the evolution of the spirit through time, and in no way entertains the
most important earlier distinctions made by Hegel of aesthetic
beauty (pertaining to the senses) and artistic
beauty (pertaining to the intellect). Hegel�s distinction may be
unfortunate for it implied two forms of beauty, which to me is impossible.
I suggest that artistic beauty
be understood to mean strictly the craftsmanship or virtuosity of the
artist.
The
history of art does not tell us much about either aesthetic
beauty or artistic beauty as an
intrinsic subject matter, but as standards presumed by observers not from
the point of view of the artists themselves�thus its great deficiency.
Nevertheless, philosophers seem to have the more authentic and profound
discussions of such subjects than art critics or historians. It is alleged
that of all the philosophers Hegel had written the most on the philosophy
of art. It is true that Hegel was a great critic as well as theoretician
on art and the philosophy of art, and his opus is immense. That does not
come as a surprise to me, for Hegel was fortunate to have as references
and role models giants who came before him, such as Kant, Mendelssohn, and
his own teachers Schelling and Fichte. Sadly his immense capacity did not
protect him from premature assumptions of racist theories of developmental
history of civilization.
I
presume that we all have read that Longinus (AD 213 - 273) is allegedly
the pioneering theoretician about the idea of the �sublime� in his
discussion of the subject of beauty in literature [Cassius Longinus, On
the Sublime, trans. W.
Rhys Roberts, (2007)]. [The manuscript was attributed also to two other
individuals from the same era as Longinus.] The distinction between
the concepts of beauty and the sublime is absolutely made clear by Moses Mendelssohn (1729-1786) in his philosophical writing.
�We have seen that
what is genuinely beautiful has definite boundaries which it may not
overstep.� [Moses Mendelssohn, Philosophical
Writings, trans. Daniel O. Dahlstrom,
Cambridge
UK
, 1997, 192-93.] However,
wrongly Immanuel Kant (1724-1804) is often credited for the
distinction between the �sublime� and the �beautiful,� in which
the main feature of the �sublime� he seems to contend to be the fact
that it is not bounded, whereas the �beautiful� he identified as
limited by the very individuality of the object or the thing. [Immanuel
Kant, (1914) Critique of Judgment,
Cosimo: NY, 2007, 64-67 (written in 1790)] It seems to me that it is
obvious that who is copying whom, certainly not Mendelssohn. Although Kant
in his book Critique of Judgment
did make references to Burke, Batteaux, Lessing et cetera, he does not
mention Mendelssohn whose views are almost identical to his writing
written some twenty years earlier. By
the way Lessing who is mentioned by Kant was Mendelssohn�s great friend
and co-editor of their literary series called Briefe, die
neuesteLiteratur betreffend (referred to as Literaturbriefe).
This
neglect or oversight by Kant of Mendelssohn is strange indeed since Kant
knew Mendelssohn quite well, for they competed on some essay writing
contest in 1763 where Mendelssohn won over Kant. Mendelssohn wrote his
piece on the subject of �beauty� and the �sublime� starting
sometime in 1754 and reworking it in 1760 for inclusion in his book
Philosophical Writings; whereas, Kant produced his
Critique of Judgment in 1790, some twenty five years later. At
any rate what comes through is that the quality of being �beautiful�
seems to involve both the act of judgment and the sensation of the thing
or object of perception [Kant, Critique of Judgment, 111-112], which seems to support
Abraham�s views. At any rate, I prefer Schopenhauer�s approach than
either approaches of Kant or Hegel. In Schopenhauer I find elements of the
Platonic Ideas/Forms�a
universality mediated by individual minds.
There
is much gobbledygook written both in the arts and the sciences. I have
read countless books on the arts, and what I learned from all that
exposure and numerous discourses over a span of forty years or more is
that writing or speaking about art authoritatively is dangerous and
limiting. It seems to me that the creative process in art might have
Platonic ideations, but the execution and delivery is firmly an inductive
process because life ultimately is experienced-reality. I cringe when
critics or philosophers speak in terms of right and wrong about art. My
approach is deceptive, in the sense that it is the subjective
�apprehension� and the pleasure of such creativity of that which is
apprehended of in the World as �representation� [Arthur Schopenhauer, Parerga
and Paralipomena,
trans. E.F.J. Payne, vol. 2, Oxford UK, 1974, 445-452] that I find
far more enlightening on the subject of �beauty� and the �sublime�
than the views of any of the other philosophers including Hegel. It seems
to me that Schopenhauer saw in the self realization or absorption of the
artist in his creation of art/beauty a great liberation from the
terrifying ever presence of the �Will.� This means beauty is in the
creator or beholder, which seems to support my views. What Julie Mehretu
was attempting in her statements was what Schopenhauer articulated
Centuries earlier, there is really nothing original about that.
III. Courage as the �Sublime�
It
seems to me that there is one kind of beauty, i.e., the beauty of courage
that only very few people seem keen to bring into discussion while most
would not even register such a thought in their minds. In fact, I think of
courage as the �sublime,� for its dimension is unbound and its
immensity overwhelming. My first encounter with the concept of courage as
a philosophical issue was reading Plato�s The Republic as text book for a philosophy undergraduate
course when I was barely eighteen. I did not do that well in that course
because my interest was in logic and rhetoric, and that book seemed to
support what I dreaded most at that time: an authoritarian household, with
a king at the top. It did not matter to me whether that king was a
philosopher or a street thug. That experience with Plato left a bad taste
with me for years. Then in graduate school I had a fresh start in an
ethics course reading Tillich�s book The
Courage to Be, (Yale, 1952) a moving dialogue of a devout
Evangelical Lutheran writing to assure himself of unbound courage to be as
opposed to giving in to dread and anxiety over nothingness.
�Tillich
brings examples of creative existential expressions of despair of men such
as Heidegger, Sartre, T.S. Elliot, Kafka, Auden, Camus, Kierkegaard,
Feuerbach, Marx and Nietzsche. The combination of the experience of
meaninglessness and of the courage to be as oneself is the key to the
development of the visual arts since the turn of the century. This is
something that those secure in both democratic conformism and
collectivism, those with the courage to be a part apart from the courage
to be, can not handle. They find it disturbing and distasteful to see art
and creativity that express the despair, meaningless and ambiguity of
Existential thought. They cannot face those who fail to interpret the man
created world of objects into subjective form. They are unable to
distinguish the genuine from the neurotic anxiety in Existentialism.�
[Edited,
abridged and expanded by Richard Schwartz, �An Outline of Paul
Tillich�s The Courage to Be, (1952),� This
is where I see great dignity in individuals who do manual odd jobs no one
else could touch. The man that digs deep into the innards of the earth to
get its minerals, or works his way in the stinky underbelly of
civilization to clean its sewer system is a true physical manifestation of
�the courage to be� that is most sublime than anything I have
encountered. To put it more concretely, for example, I am always moved by
people who collect and remove society�s garbage, take care of the dead
both human beings and animals, serve at cafes and restaurants even when
they are rude. My great respect to immigrant workers and strangers in any
settled society is simply an extension of that one recognition of the
beauty of courage as sublime. I tell my wife that I lack that type of
courage to accept my circumstance in life, and I infuriate her more when I
add that if I win over a hundred million dollars in a lottery, I can
afford to be poor and live without pretentions wearing sandals and jelebia
with humility.
I always remember with
awe the kind dignity of teenager Ryan Wayne White
(1971 � 1990), who knowing fully well of his imminent death and yet
faced panicking and hostile parents and teachers with respect and
understanding. They kicked him out of middle-school for he was diagnosed
with little understood HIV/AIDS at the time.
His short life was a sublime life. And I believe that every child
with deformity or congenital defect or terminal disease who gets up every
morning and faces his or her grim reality is the most beautiful individual
in life. In other words, the �courage to be� means living without
complaint and without giving-up and without taking oneself as the center
of the Universe.
Political
courage is also sublime when practiced against an entrenched power
structure and the leadership thereof. There were exemplary instances in
history where sublime act of courage is manifested by few under most
daunting situations. For example, the three hundred Spartans facing off
half a million Persian soldiers at Thermopile, the throng of very poorly
armed patriotic Ethiopians standing firm against well-equipped modern army
of Italy in several parts of Ethiopia, or the handful Ethiopian opposition
political parties engaging the violence of Meles Zenawi�s Government and
its security machine in 2005 and now et cetera. Such are acts of sublime
courage.
Of
course, the ultimate courage is to forgive those who do harm us, as the
Christ did forgive from the Cross, in great pain, those who were
responsible for his suffering. Such a life would be authentic and sublime.
When Abraham expressed in our discourse at the Arboretum about his dream
of becoming a �park ranger,� what he was seeking was precisely an
authentic and sublime life, fully expressing the notion of �the courage
to be.�
Conclusion
It
is often argued by a number of artists I know that an artist should not
blabber about his/her work for the work speaks for itself. There is no
need to muddy the water by using substitution (words) in trying to
elaborate or explain that which is presented already. I agree with that
sentiment to a great extent. However, such limitations would have deprived
us also the superb writings of great artists, such as Joshua Reynolds
[Joshua Reynolds, Seven Discourses
on Art, BiblioBazar, 2006], Leo Tolstoy [Leo Tolstoy, What
is Art, Penguin, 1995], Ben Shahn [Ben Shahn,
The Shape of Content, Harvard, 1957] et cetera, for the
treatment or discourse on art may in itself be considered as literature of
the first quality as evidenced by the writers I cited here. For example,
if we consider Shahn�s rather slim work, it is far more lucid and deeply
penetrating into the very soul of the artist, which form of writing is far
more authentic than any historian or critic had written on the subject of
content in art in far thicker books.
Although
there may be very little connection between ethical theories and most real
life-behavior of people, it is not hurtful to have some understanding of
moral and ethical principles in society. I extend my observations on
�beauty� and the �sublime� to cover political and social
engagements. A good illustration would be the courageous activities of the
leaders of Medrek both here and back home in
Ethiopia
. The leaders of Medrek and their supporters have demonstrated their
courage in facing brutal and savage individuals who have acquired
illegally state power in
Ethiopia
. This opposition movement and real-time stand against the tyranny of the
current Ethiopian Government leaders must be seen as a �sublime� act
of singular courage. And Birtukan Mideksa from her prison cell is the
personification of that singular sublime courage of opposition. She is awe
inspiring, and her impact immense in the political and social lives of
great many Ethiopians. Ω
Tecola
W. Hagos
Washington
DC
May
7, 2010
Art
and the CIA
by
Richard Cummings
In
the play ART, someone buys an abstract painting at an enormous price,
while his friends ponder how they are going to tell him that it is
inherently worthless. In the debate about abstraction and whether it was
entirely some sort of hoax, the new traditionalists ridicule its
"flatness" and its absence of narrative, while defenders of
abstraction insist that representative art is a form of nostalgia that
modernism sought to eliminate. The defenders are definitely losing ground,
but one wonders why they were ever regarded as credible.
The
point that most art critics miss is that art is also a form of commerce,
and not antithetical to it. The god of art is the art market. And so one
might ask, "How did a Jackson Pollock get to be worth so much
money?" Part of it had to do with the Cold War, which not only
bloated the military budget, but distorted the art market as well.
Faux
genius and con man Clement Greenberg was at the center of the scam. A
former itinerant necktie salesman, Greenberg teamed up with struggling
abstract artist and mountebank, Barnett Newman, to promote a vision of art
that conveniently coincided with the objectives of the US Cold War
Establishment. Indeed, Greenberg argued that the avant-garde required the
support of
America
�s elite classes, a self-serving concept that would promote his personal
interests as a collector.
As
the competing ideologies of capitalism and communism clashed after the
Second World War, the question of "What is art?" became a
significant issue in the struggle for dominance. Was art a vehicle of
state propaganda to glorify a proletarian revolution or depict an evil
Hitler in his bunker at the end of the heroic struggle against fascism
(never mind about the Hitler-Stalin pact), or was it the product of
individual creativity unrestrained by governmental control and censorship?
But
since
America
was then in the throes of one of its tedious puritanical backlashes, the
sensuality of great Western art, as represented by say, Goya�s
"Naked Maja," was out of the question. Deriving their central
thesis from Islamic art that representation of the sensual human form was
interdicted by the sublime, the new Abstract Expressionists fit neatly
into what the American intelligence community desperately needed to rebut
Soviet representational propaganda; an art that was highly individualistic
but which did not offend the sensibilities of conservative religion. A
Baptist preacher or Bishop Sheen could laugh at a Pollock, but he could
not condemn it as obscene. Yet because "modern art" was widely
derided, it needed a boost from an invisible sponsor, which would turn out
to be the CIA.
In
this milieu Clement Greenberg came forth in support of the new art. Yes,
the canvas was flat, and it should be covered flatly by paint in
abstraction, so beauty would be destroyed in the name of the sublime. And
Museum
of
Modern Art
(MoMA) director Richard Barr heralded this view when he quoted
Greenberg�s co-conspirator, Newman, who infamously proclaimed, "The
impulse of modern art was to destroy beauty." Barr went even further
� God was dead and had been replaced by Abstract Expressionism.
The
more Greenberg wrote in promotion of the Abstract Expressionists, and
particularly Pollock�s "action painting," which involved
dripping paint on the canvas, the more he collected them at minimal prices
before he had made them famous. And as he increased his own power and
influence, the more people wanted to buy these paintings, which served
Greenberg�s real personal objective; to make himself rich.
Fortunately
for him, like the military industrial complex, he had a helping hand in
the federal government. As Frances Stoner Saunders explains in her
brilliant book, Who
Paid the Piper � The CIA and the Cultural Cold War, the CIA
covertly supported the Abstract Expressionist movement by funding exhibits
all over the world in promotion of the idea that the culture of freedom
was superior to the culture of slavery, and by covertly promoting the
purchasing of works by various private collections. Indeed, the CIA named
its biggest front in
Europe
the Congress for Cultural Freedom. It worked. Soviet art became a laughing
stock, and
New York
became the center of the art world, not
Paris
, where Picasso, a long-time member of the Communist party and winner of
the Stalin Peace Prize (who can forget his doves of peace?), still reigned
supreme.
The
CIA had stolen the show from Picasso, taking art a step further into a
near mystical expression of unfettered human liberty in the spirit of free
enterprise. Nelson Rockefeller, whose family created the MoMA, actually
referred to Abstract Expressionism as "free enterprise
painting." But like so many Rockefeller ventures, it was state
supported, so that his own collection of Abstract Expressionist works
ended up being worth a considerable fortune.
But
why, then, did it come to an end? The Cold War exploded into the Vietnam
War and rebellion overtook the arts. The social revolution of the Sixties
brought with it Pop Art, Op Art, and various forms of social protest art,
forcing Abstract Expressionism to the sidelines, even if prices were still
good. Confronted with James Rosenquist�s "F-111," abstraction
lost its force. Even more than this, the answer lies in a paraphrasing of
a remark by comedian Mort Sahl about why the student movement ended.
"The government withdrew its funding."
June
20, 2002
Richard
Cummings [send him mail] has
taught at the University of Addis Ababa, Ethiopia, the University of the
West Indies,
Barbados
, and St. Catherine�s College Cambridge. He holds the PhD in Social and
Political Sciences from
Cambridge
University
and "completed with distinction" the 21st Session at
Cornell
University
, of The School of Criticism and Theory. He is the author of the comedy,
"Soccer Moms From Hell" (recently produced in
New York
) and the forthcoming novel, The Immortalists.
[https://www.lewrockwell.com/orig3/cummings3.html.
It is a snapshot of the page as it appeared on Apr 19, 2010.]
|